Interpreting posterior probabilities in the context of weakly informative priors

Normal Deviate 2015-07-01

Nathan Lemoine writes:

I’m an ecologist, and I typically work with small sample sizes from field experiments, which have highly variable data. I analyze almost all of my data now using hierarchical models, but I’ve been wondering about my interpretation of the posterior distributions. I’ve read your blog, several of your papers (Gelman and Weakliem, Gelman and Carlin), and your excellent BDA book, and I was wondering if I could ask your advice/opinion on my interpretation of posterior probabilities.

I’ve thought of 95% posterior credible intervals as a good way to estimate effect size, but I still see many researchers use them in something akin to null hypothesis testing: “The 95% interval included zero, and therefore the pattern was not significant”. I tend not to do that. Since I work with small sample sizes and variable data, it seems as though I’m unlikely to find a “significant effect” unless I’m vastly overestimating the true effect size (Type M error) or unless the true effect size is enormous (a rarity). More often than not, I find ‘suggestive’, but not ‘significant’ effects.

In such cases, I calculate one-tailed posterior probabilities that the effect is positive (or negative) and report that along with estimates of the effect size. For example, I might say something like

“Foliar damage tended to be slightly higher in ‘Ambient’ treatments, although the difference between treatments was small and variable (Pr(Ambient>Warmed) = 0.86, CI95 = 2.3% less – 6.9% more damage).”

By giving the probability of an effect as well as an estimate of the effect size, I find this to be more informative than simply saying ‘not significant’. This allows researchers to make their own judgements on importance, rather than defining importance for them by p < 0.05. I know that such one-tailed probabilities can be inaccurate when using flat priors, but I place weakly informative priors ( N(0,1) or N(0,2) ) on all parameters in an attempt to avoid such overestimates unless strongly supported by my small sample sizes.

I was wondering if you agree with this philosophy of data reporting and interpretation, or if I’m misusing the posterior probabilities. I’ve done some research on this, but I can’t find anyone that’s offered a solid opinion on this. Based on my reading and the few interactions I’ve had with others, it seems that the strength of posterior probabilities compared to p-values is that they allow for such fluid interpretation (what’s the probability the effect is positive? what’s the probability the effect > 5? etc.), whereas p-values simply tell you “if the null hypothesis is true, theres a 70 or 80% chance I could observe an effect as strong as mine by chance alone”. I prefer to give the probability of an effect bounded by the CI of the effect to give the most transparent interpretation possible.

My reply:

My short answer is that this is addressed in this post:

If you believe your prior, then yes, it makes sense to report posterior probabilities as you do. Typically, though, we use flat priors even though we have pretty strong knowledge that parameters are close to 0 (this is consistent with the fact that we see lots of estimates that are 1 or 2 se’s from 0, but very few that are 4 or 6 se’s from 0). So, really, if you want to make such a statement I think you’d want a more informative prior that shrinks to 0. If, for whatever reason, you don’t want to assign such a prior, then you have to be a bit more careful about interpreting those posterior probabilities.

In your case, you’re using weakly-informative priors such as N(0,1), this is less of a concern. Ultimately I guess the way to go is to embed any problem in a hierarchical meta-analysis so that the prior makes sense in the context of the problem. But, yeah, I’ve been using N(0,1) a lot myself lately.

The post Interpreting posterior probabilities in the context of weakly informative priors appeared first on Statistical Modeling, Causal Inference, and Social Science.