Positive Definite Quadratic Forms
Power Overwhelming 2018-03-12
I’m reading through Primes of the Form , by David Cox (link; it’s good!). Here are the high-level notes I took on the first chapter, which is about the theory of quadratic forms.
(Meta point re blog: I’m probably going to start posting more and more of these more high-level notes/sketches on this blog on topics that I’ve been just learning. Up til now I’ve been mostly only posting things that I understand well and for which I have a very polished exposition. But the perfect is the enemy of the good here; given that I’m taking these notes for my own sake, I may as well share them to help others.)
1. Overview
Definition 1
For us a quadratic form is a polynomial , where
,
,
are some integers. We say that it is primitive if
.
For example, we have the famous quadratic form
As readers are probably aware, we can say a lot about exactly which integers can be represented by : by Fermat’s Christmas theorem, the primes
(and
) can all be written as the sum of two squares, while the primes
cannot. For convenience, let us say that:
Definition 2
Let be a quadratic form. We say it represents the integer
if there exists
with
. Moreover,
properly represents
if one can find such
and
which are also relatively prime.
The basic question is: what can we say about which primes/integers are properly represented by a quadratic form? In fact, we will later restrict our attention to “positive definite” forms (described later).
For example, Fermat’s Christmas theorem now rewrites as:
Theorem 3 (Fermat’s Christmas theorem for primes)
An odd prime is (properly) represented by
if and only if
.
The proof of this is classical, see for example my olympiad handout. We also have the formulation for odd integers:
Theorem 4 (Fermat’s Christmas theorem for odd integers)
An odd integer is properly represented by
if and only if all prime factors of
are
.
Proof: For the “if” direction, we use the fact that is multiplicative in the sense that
For the “only if” part we use the fact that if a multiple of a prime is properly represented by
, then so is
. This follows by noticing that if
(and
) then
.
Tangential remark: the two ideas in the proof will grow up in the following way.
- The fact that
“multiplies nicely” will grow up to become the so-called composition of quadratic forms.
- The second fact will not generalize for an arbitrary form
. Instead, we will see that if a multiple of
is represented by a form
then some form of the same “discriminant” will represent the prime
, but this form need not be the same as
itself.
2. Equivalence of forms, and the discriminant
The first thing we should do is figure out when two forms are essentially the same: for example, and
should clearly be considered the same. More generally, if we think of
as acting on
and
is any automorphism of
, then
should be considered the same as
. Specifically,
Definition 5
Two forms and
said to be equivalent if there exists
such that . We have
and so we say the equivalence is
- a proper equivalence if
, and
- an improper equivalence if
.
So we generally will only care about forms up to proper equivalence. (It will be useful to distinguish between proper/improper equivalence later.)
Naturally we seek some invariants under this operation. By far the most important is:
Definition 6
The discriminant of a quadratic form is defined as
The discriminant is invariant under equivalence (check this). Note also that we also have .
Observe that we have
So if and
(thus
too) then
for all
. Such quadratic forms are called positive definite, and we will restrict our attention to these forms.
Now that we have this invariant, we may as well classify equivalence classes of quadratic forms for a fixed discriminant. It turns out this can be done explicitly.
Definition 7
A quadratic form is reduced if
- it is primitive and positive definite,
-
, and
-
if either
or
.
Exercise 8
Check there only finitely many reduced forms of a fixed discriminant.
Then the big huge theorem is:
Theorem 9 (Reduced forms give a set of representatives)
Every primitive positive definite form of discriminant is properly equivalent to a unique reduced form. We call this the reduction of
.
Proof: Omitted due to length, but completely elementary. It is a reduction argument with some number of cases.
Thus, for any discriminant we can consider the set
which will be the equivalence classes of positive definite of discriminant . By abuse of notation we will also consider it as the set of equivalence classes of primitive positive definite forms of discriminant
.
We also define ; by the exercise,
. This is called the class number.
Moreover, we have , because we can take
for
and
for
. We call this form the principal form.
3. Tables of quadratic forms
Example 10 (Examples of quadratic forms with ,
)
The following discriminants have class number , hence having only the principal form:
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
This is in fact the complete list when .
Example 11 (Examples of quadratic forms with ,
)
The following discriminants have class number , hence having only the principal form:
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
-
, with form
.
This is in fact the complete list when .
Example 12 (More examples of quadratic forms)
Here are tables for small discriminants with . When
we have
-
, with
forms
and
.
-
, with
forms
and
.
-
, with
forms
and
.
-
, with
forms
and
.
-
, with
forms
and
.
-
, with
forms
and
.
As for we have
-
, with
forms
and
.
-
, with
forms
and
.
-
, with
forms
and
.
-
, with
forms
,
and
.
Example 13 (Even More Examples of quadratic forms)
Here are some more selected examples:
-
has
forms
,
and
.
-
has
forms
and
.
-
has
forms
,
and
.
4. The Character
We can now connect this to primes as follows. Earlier we played with
, and observed that for odd primes
,
if and only if some multiple of
is properly represented by
.
Our generalization is as follows:
Theorem 14 (Primes represented by some quadratic form)
Let be a discriminant, and let
be an odd prime. Then the following are equivalent:
-
, i.e.
is a quadratic residue modulo
.
- The prime
is (properly) represented by some reduced quadratic form in
.
This generalizes our result for , but note that it uses
in an essential way! That is: if
, we know
is represented by some quadratic form of discriminant
\dots but only since
do we know that this form reduces to
.
Proof: First assume WLOG that and
. Thus
, since otherwise this would imply
. Then
hence .
The converse direction is amusing: let for integers
,
. Consider the quadratic form
It is primitive of discriminant and
. Now
may not be reduced, but that’s fine: just take the reduction of
, which must also properly represent
.
Thus to every discriminant we can attach the Legendre character (is that the name?), which is a homomorphism
with the property that if is a rational prime not dividing
, then
. This is abuse of notation since I should technically write
, but there is no harm done: one can check by quadratic reciprocity that if
then
. Thus our previous result becomes:
Theorem 15 ( consists of representable primes)
Let be prime. Then
if and only if some quadratic form in
represents
.
As a corollary of this, using the fact that one can prove that
Corollary 16 (Fermat-type results for )
Let be a prime. Then
is
- of the form
if and only if
.
- of the form
if and only if
.
- of the form
if and only if
.
Proof: The congruence conditions are equivalent to , and as before the only point is that the only reduced quadratic form for these
is the principal one.
5. Genus theory
What if ? Sometimes, we can still figure out which primes go where just by taking mods.
Let . Then it represents some residue classes of
. In that case we call the set of residue classes represented the genus of the quadratic form
.
Example 17 (Genus theory of )
Consider , with
We consider the two elements of :
-
represents
.
-
represents
.
Now suppose for example that . It must be represented by one of these two quadratic forms, but the latter form is never
and so it must be the first one. Thus we conclude that
-
if and only if
.
-
if and only if
.
The thing that makes this work is that each genus appears exactly once. We are not always so lucky: for example when we have that
Example 18 (Genus theory of )
The two elements of are:
-
, which represents exactly the
elements of
.
-
, which also represents exactly the
elements of
.
So the best we can conclude is that OR
if and only if
This is because the two distinct quadratic forms of discriminant
happen to have the same genus.
We now prove that:
Theorem 19 (Genii are cosets of )
Let be a discriminant and consider the Legendre character
.
- The genus of the principal form of discriminant
constitutes a subgroup
of
, which we call the principal genus.
- Any genus of a quadratic form in
is a coset of the principal genus
in
.
Proof: For the first part, we aim to show is multiplicatively closed. For
,
we use the fact that
For , we instead appeal to another “magic” identity
and it follows from here that is actually the set of squares in
, which is obviously a subgroup.
Now we show that other quadratic forms have genus equal to a coset of the principal genus. For , with
we can write
and thus the desired coset is shown to be . As for
, we have
so the desired coset is also , since
was the set of squares.
Thus every genus is a coset of in
. Thus:
Definition 20
We define the quotient group
which is the set of all genuses in discriminant . One can view this as an abelian group by coset multiplication.
Thus there is a natural map
(The map is surjective by Theorem~14.) We also remark than is quite well-behaved:
Proposition 21 (Structure of )
The group is isomorphic to
for some integer
.
Proof: Observe that contains all the squares of
: if
is the principal form then
. Thus claim each element of
has order at most
, which implies the result since
is a finite abelian group.
In fact, one can compute the order of exactly, but for this post I Will just state the result.
Theorem 22 (Order of )
Let be a discriminant, and let
be the number of distinct odd primes which divide
. Define
by:
-
if
.
-
if
and
.
-
if
and
.
-
if
and
.
-
if
and
.
Then .
6. Composition
We have already used once the nice identity
We are going to try and generalize this for any two quadratic forms in . Specifically,
Proposition 23 (Composition defines a group operation)
Let . Then there is a unique
and bilinear forms
for
such that
-
.
-
.
-
.
In fact, without the latter two constraints we would instead have and
, and each choice of signs would yield one of four (possibly different) forms. So requiring both signs to be positive makes this operation well-defined. (This is why we like proper equivalence; it gives us a well-defined group structure, whereas with improper equivalence it would be impossible to put a group structure on the forms above.)
Taking this for granted, we then have that
Theorem 24 (Form class group)
Let ,
be a discriminant. Then
becomes an abelian group under composition, where
- The identity of
is the principal form, and
- The inverse of the form
is
.
This group is called the form class group.
We then have a group homomorphism
Observe that and
are inverses and that their
images coincide (being improperly equivalent); this is expressed in the fact that
has elements of order
. As another corollary, the number of elements of
with a given genus is always a power of two.
We now define:
Definition 25
An integer is convenient if the following equivalent conditions hold:
- The principal form
is the only reduced form with the principal genus.
-
is injective (hence an isomorphism).
-
.
Thus we arrive at the following corollary:
Corollary 26 (Convenient numbers have nice representations)
Let be convenient. Then
is of the form
if and only if
lies in the principal genus.
Hence the represent-ability depends only on .
OEIS A000926 lists 65 convenient numbers. This sequence is known to be complete except for at most one more number; moreover the list is complete assuming the Grand Riemann Hypothesis.
7. Cubic and quartic reciprocity
To treat the cases where is not convenient, the correct thing to do is develop class field theory. However, we can still make a little bit more progress if we bring higher reciprocity theorems to bear: we’ll handle the cases
and
, two examples of numbers which are not convenient.
7.1. Cubic reciprocity
First, we prove that
To do this we use cubic reciprocity, which requires working in the Eisenstein integers where
is a cube root of unity. There are six units in
(the sixth roots of unity), hence each nonzero number has six associates (differing by a unit), and the ring is in fact a PID.
Now if we let be a prime not dividing
, and
is coprime to
, then we can define the cubic Legendre symbol by setting
Moreover, we can define a primary prime to be one such that
; given any prime exactly one of the six associates is primary. We then have the following reciprocity theorem:
Theorem 28 (Cubic reciprocity)
If and
are disjoint primary primes in
then
We also have the following supplementary laws: if , then
The first supplementary law is for the unit (analogous to ) while the second reciprocity law handles the prime divisors of
(analogous to
.)
We can tie this back into as follows. If
is a rational prime then it is represented by
, and thus we can put
for some prime
,
. Consequently, we have a natural isomorphism
Therefore, we see that a given is a cubic residue if and only if
.
In particular, we have the following corollary, which is all we will need:
Corollary 29 (When is a cubic residue)
Let be a rational prime,
. Write
with
primary. Then
is a cubic residue modulo
if and only if
.
Proof: By cubic reciprocity:
Now we give the proof of Theorem~27. Proof: First assume
Let be primary, noting that
. Now clearly
, so done by corollary.
For the converse, assume ,
with
primary and
. If we set
for integers
and
, then the fact that
and
is enough to imply that
(check it!). Moreover,
as desired.
7.2. Quartic reciprocity
This time we work in , for which there are four units
,
. A prime is primary if
; every prime not dividing
has a unique associate which is primary. Then we can as before define
where is primary, and
is nonzero mod
. As before
,
we have that
is a quartic residue modulo
if and only if
thanks to the isomorphism
Now we have
Theorem 30 (Quartic reciprocity)
If and
are distinct primary primes in
then
We also have supplementary laws that state that if is primary, then
Again, the first law handles units, and the second law handles the prime divisors of . The corollary we care about this time in fact uses only the supplemental laws:
Corollary 31 (When is a quartic residue)
Let be a prime, and put
with
primary. Then
and in particular is a quartic residue modulo
if and only if
.
Proof: Note that and applying the above. Therefore
Now we assumed is primary. We claim that
Note that since was is divisible by
, hence
divides
. Thus
since is odd and
is even. Finally,
From here we quickly deduce
Theorem 32 (On )
If is prime, then
if and only if
and
is a quartic residue modulo
.